01 June 2025

Sartre’s Concepts of Freedom and Existential Choice

Jean-Paul Sartre’s Concepts of Freedom and Existential Choice: An Existentialist Framework

Sartre’s Concepts of Freedom and Existential Choice

“Man is condemned to be free; because once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he does. It is up to you to give [life] a meaning.”
― Jean-Paul Sartre

Abstract
"This paper provides an in-depth exploration of Jean-Paul Sartre's existentialist philosophy, particularly focusing on the intertwined concepts of freedom and existential choice. Sartre’s idea that "existence precedes essence" forms the cornerstone of his belief in radical human freedom and the ethical demands it places on individuals. Drawing from major works such as Being and Nothingness and Existentialism Is a Humanism, this paper critically examines how Sartre envisions freedom as both a blessing and a burden, and how existential choice plays a central role in the construction of selfhood, morality, and authenticity. The essay also explores Sartre's ideas through literary examples and analyzes contemporary relevance and critiques of his theory.

Introduction

Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980), a towering figure in 20th-century philosophy, championed a radical form of existentialism that positioned human freedom at its core. More than a metaphysical idea, Sartre's notion of freedom is a lived, inescapable reality. His existentialist axiom that "existence precedes essence" (Sartre, 2007) subverts traditional essentialist views by declaring that human beings must first exist and then define themselves through acts of choice. Thus, Sartre intertwines freedom with responsibility, arguing that we are "condemned to be free" because we cannot escape the burden of shaping our lives through conscious decisions.

This essay explores Sartre's concepts of freedom and existential choice by analyzing key elements of his philosophy. It begins by outlining Sartre's metaphysical categories of being, especially his distinction between being-in-itself and being-for-itself. It then delves into his understanding of freedom, responsibility, and anguish. Following this, it examines the ideas of existential choice and authenticity, contrasting them with the concept of "bad faith." The essay also evaluates Sartre’s literary expressions of these themes and concludes with a discussion on contemporary relevance and philosophical critiques of his theories.

1. Sartre's Ontology: Being-in-Itself and Being-for-Itself

Sartre’s magnum opus, Being and Nothingness (1943/1956), lays the ontological foundation for his existentialist ethics. He introduces two fundamental modes of being: être-en-soi (being-in-itself) and être-pour-soi (being-for-itself).

Being-in-itself characterizes inanimate objects, which are self-contained, complete, and without consciousness. These entities are what they are—fixed and static. In contrast, human consciousness is being-for-itself. It is defined not by what it is but by its capacity to negate, imagine, and transcend itself. Consciousness is, in Sartre’s words, a "nothingness" (Sartre, 1956), a gap between the self and the world that enables freedom.

Through this gap, human beings can distance themselves from their facticity—the concrete realities of their existence—and choose what to make of them. It is this unique capacity that gives rise to freedom. Unlike a stone or a tree, a human is not bound to a single essence or purpose. Instead, the self is a project to be constructed over time.

2. The Nature of Freedom: Ontological and Practical Dimensions

Sartre's concept of freedom is ontological; it is not merely a political or psychological condition but an inherent feature of human existence. He insists that humans are free "not to be what they are and to be what they are not" (Sartre, 1956, p. 59). This radical freedom stems from consciousness’s ability to negate the given and to posit future possibilities.

Freedom, however, is double-edged. It provides the individual with infinite potential but also imposes absolute responsibility. Sartre famously declares that we are "condemned to be free" (Sartre, 2007). There is no escape from this freedom, even when we seek to deny it. For Sartre, every action or inaction is a choice. Even when external circumstances seem overwhelming, individuals retain the freedom to choose their response.

This recognition of freedom often leads to anguish. Sartre defines anguish as the realization of one’s total responsibility, not just for oneself but for humanity. In choosing for ourselves, we set an example and model for others. This universalizing aspect of choice gives existentialism an ethical dimension without resorting to objective moral laws.

3. Existential Choice: Responsibility in Action

Existential choice is the lived enactment of freedom. Without essence or predetermined moral codes, humans must create meaning through choices. Sartre believes that values are not discovered but invented.

In Existentialism Is a Humanism, he recounts the example of a young man choosing between joining the Resistance or caring for his mother during World War II. There is no universal answer to this dilemma. The young man must choose and, in so doing, define himself (Sartre, 2007). This story encapsulates Sartre’s belief that existential choice is both unavoidable and defining.

Furthermore, choices are not made in a vacuum. They are always contextual, shaped by personal and historical conditions. Yet Sartre resists determinism. Even within constraints, he argues, there remains the ability to choose—even if only the choice of how to respond.

4. Bad Faith and Authenticity

A central concern in Sartre’s ethics is the contrast between authenticity and bad faith (mauvaise foi). Bad faith is the denial of one’s own freedom. It is a form of self-deception where individuals adopt fixed roles or identities to escape the anxiety of freedom.

Sartre provides illustrative examples: the overly conscientious waiter who becomes the role rather than playing it, or the woman on a date who passively avoids her own sexual agency. These individuals act as if they are objects, denying their transcendence and responsibility (Sartre, 1956).

Authenticity, by contrast, involves accepting and embracing one's freedom. It means acknowledging that one is not a fixed identity but a project in the making. Authentic individuals act with awareness that they are responsible for what they become. They do not hide behind roles or external authorities but create meaning through conscious engagement with their choices.

5. Freedom and the Gaze of the Other

Sartre expands his understanding of freedom by analyzing interpersonal relationships. In Being and Nothingness, he introduces the idea of "the look" (le regard) of the Other. When we perceive ourselves being seen by others, we become objects in their consciousness. This experience can threaten our sense of freedom, making us aware of how others can define or limit us.

However, Sartre maintains that even in the face of the Other’s gaze, we retain the power to choose how to respond. We can internalize their judgment, rebel against it, or redefine ourselves in spite of it. The gaze is thus both a challenge and a condition for self-awareness.

6. Sartre in Literature: Freedom Embodied

Sartre’s literary works serve as dramatizations of his philosophical ideas. In Nausea (1938/1964), protagonist Roquentin grapples with the absurdity of existence. Objects lose their meaning, and he is haunted by the realization that life has no inherent purpose. This confrontation with contingency is a hallmark of existential freedom.

In No Exit (1944/1989), three characters are trapped in a room for eternity, each serving as the Other to the others. The famous line "Hell is other people" reflects the difficulty of maintaining authenticity in the presence of judgment. Yet even here, Sartre suggests that the path to freedom lies in refusing to be defined by others.

These literary expressions reinforce the lived reality of existential freedom. They underscore Sartre's belief that freedom is not abstract but visceral, embedded in concrete situations.

7. Criticisms and Challenges

While Sartre’s philosophy has been celebrated, it has also attracted substantial criticism. One of the main critiques comes from Simone de Beauvoir, who, though largely aligned with Sartre, argues in The Ethics of Ambiguity (1948/1976) that his focus on freedom can overlook the material and social conditions that limit individual agency. She emphasizes that authentic freedom must involve the freedom of others as well.

From a psychoanalytic perspective, Sartre's rejection of the unconscious has been questioned. Freud and Lacan argue that much of human behavior is influenced by unconscious drives, challenging the idea of total self-transparency and rational choice.

Moreover, critics like Herbert Marcuse and Alasdair MacIntyre have argued that Sartre’s moral framework is too subjective. If values are wholly self-created, how can we criticize harmful actions or establish a coherent ethical system?

Despite these critiques, Sartre’s emphasis on choice and responsibility has influenced numerous fields, from psychology and education to literature and political theory.

8. Contemporary Relevance

Sartre’s philosophy remains strikingly relevant in today’s world. In an era marked by political polarization, existential threats, and identity crises, the existentialist call to live authentically and take responsibility resonates deeply.

Existential therapy, for example, draws on Sartrean ideas to help clients confront their freedom and construct meaningful lives (Yalom, 1980). In education, pedagogies based on critical thinking and autonomy reflect existentialist values.

Moreover, movements for social justice often rely on existential principles: the idea that individuals and groups can redefine themselves and resist imposed identities. Sartre's later commitment to Marxism and anti-colonialism shows his awareness that freedom must also be political and collective.

Conclusion

Jean-Paul Sartre’s concepts of freedom and existential choice remain central to existentialist thought and continue to influence contemporary discourse. Through his ontological distinction between being-in-itself and being-for-itself, Sartre lays the foundation for a philosophy that locates human essence in freedom. This freedom is both a source of creativity and a heavy burden, demanding responsibility and authenticity.

Sartre’s vision of existential choice challenges us to live deliberately, to embrace our role as authors of our own existence, and to accept the consequences of our actions. Though not without criticism, his philosophy offers a compelling framework for understanding human agency in an uncertain world.

Ultimately, Sartre does not offer comfort or easy answers. Instead, he invites us to confront our freedom head-on, recognizing that in doing so, we begin to create ourselves." (Source: ChatGPT 2925)

References

Beauvoir, S. de. (1976). The ethics of ambiguity (B. Frechtman, Trans.). Citadel Press. (Original work published 1948)

Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness: An essay in phenomenological ontology (H. E. Barnes, Trans.). Washington Square Press. (Original work published 1943)

Sartre, J.-P. (1964). Nausea (L. Alexander, Trans.). New Directions. (Original work published 1938)

Sartre, J.-P. (1989). No exit and three other plays (S. Gilbert, Trans.). Vintage International. (Original work published 1944)

Sartre, J.-P. (2007). Existentialism is a humanism (C. Macomber, Trans.). Yale University Press. (Original work published 1946)

Yalom, I. D. (1980). Existential psychotherapy. Basic Books.

Report: ChatGPT 2025

Jean-Paul Sartre and Existential Choice

Top Image: Microsoft Copilot 2025