Existential-phenomenological motivation situates the human drive to act within the ontological structure of existence itself.
Introduction
Existential-phenomenological motivation refers to the dynamic orientation of human existence as understood through the intersecting traditions of existentialism and phenomenology. Rather than treating motivation as a mechanistic drive reducible to biological impulses or external stimuli, this approach conceives it as an ontological and experiential phenomenon—a movement of consciousness and being toward meaning. The foundational works of Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, later developed in existential psychology by Viktor Frankl, Rollo May, and Irvin Yalom, reveal motivation as a structure of intentionality, freedom, and care.
Traditional psychological models—from behaviorism to cognitive theory—have often sought to quantify motivation as an observable variable, focusing on reinforcement, goal-setting, or incentive mechanisms. Yet, existential and phenomenological perspectives argue that these accounts overlook the lived and qualitative dimension of human striving. To be motivated, in this sense, is to be a self-interpreting being whose existence is defined by projects, meaning, and temporality. The following essay explores existential-phenomenological motivation through its philosophical foundations, psychological interpretations, and implications for understanding the human condition.
Phenomenology and the Ground of MotivationEdmund Husserl’s phenomenology provides the epistemological grounding for existential understandings of motivation. Husserl (1931/2012) defined consciousness as intentional: it is always directed toward something, whether real or imagined. Motivation therefore arises not from an isolated internal state but from the intentional structure of consciousness—the “aboutness” that constitutes meaning. As Moran (2000) explains, phenomenology “brings to light the essential structure of lived experience” (p. 4). Motivation, seen phenomenologically, is the directional quality of this experience: the way consciousness stretches toward fulfillment or significance.
Husserl’s notion of the lifeworld (Lebenswelt) is central here. It denotes the pre-theoretical horizon in which meaning is experienced prior to scientific abstraction (Husserl, 1970). Within the lifeworld, value and purpose are not externally imposed but discovered through engagement with the world. Consequently, motivation is always contextual and lived; it cannot be abstracted from the embodied and temporal situation of the person.
Phenomenological psychologists such as Giorgi (2009) emphasize that motivation should be studied as a phenomenon revealed in experience, not as a hypothetical construct. Rather than asking what causes motivation, the phenomenologist asks how motivation appears in lived life. This reorientation moves psychology from causal explanation to descriptive understanding. Motivation, in this framework, is the lived sense of being drawn toward possibilities—an affective-intentional orientation embedded in existence itself.
Heidegger and the Ontological TurnMartin Heidegger transformed Husserl’s phenomenology into a fundamental ontology, grounding motivation not in epistemology but in the structure of Being. In Being and Time (1927/1962), he identifies care (Sorge) as the essential constitution of human existence (Dasein). Care signifies that humans are always already involved with the world; they are concerned about their being and the beings they encounter. Motivation, in this ontological light, is a manifestation of care—it is the existential movement of concernful involvement with one’s possibilities.
Heidegger’s analysis of thrownness (Geworfenheit) reveals that motivation arises from our finite situation: we are “thrown” into conditions we did not choose, yet we must respond to them through our projects. Motivation thus becomes a response to the facticity of existence, the way Dasein takes up its thrown situation and projects itself into the future. The existential structure of being-toward-possibility gives motivation its temporal and forward-oriented nature (Heidegger, 1962).
Authentic motivation, for Heidegger, emerges when one assumes responsibility for one’s being, confronting mortality and finitude. Inauthentic motivation, by contrast, arises when one conforms to the impersonal dictates of “the They” (das Man), pursuing socially prescribed goals rather than existential meaning. Authentic motivation therefore presupposes resoluteness (Entschlossenheit)—a commitment to live in accordance with one’s own understanding of Being. Motivation is no longer about attaining satisfaction but about actualizing one’s possibilities in the face of death, the ultimate horizon of existence.
Heidegger’s contribution lies in disclosing the ontological depth of motivation. It is not an empirical variable but a manifestation of care—the very structure of existence through which the world matters to us. In every act of striving, even the most mundane, lies a disclosure of being-in-the-world.
Sartre: Freedom, Negation, and ProjectJean-Paul Sartre radicalized the phenomenological view of motivation by grounding it in freedom and negation. In Being and Nothingness (1943/2003), he describes consciousness (for-itself) as a “nothingness” that transcends the given. Because consciousness is self-negating—it is always beyond what it is—it creates meaning through projection toward the not-yet. Motivation, for Sartre, is this self-transcending movement of consciousness toward a chosen future.
Rejecting determinism, Sartre maintains that every motive is freely constituted. To be motivated is not to be driven by causal forces but to choose one’s ends and interpret one’s situation accordingly. The project (projet) is Sartre’s key concept: a total structure that organizes all specific acts of motivation around a self-chosen purpose. For instance, the desire to become an artist, parent, or scholar expresses a global project of being that lends coherence to one’s actions.
Sartre’s notion of bad faith (mauvaise foi) illuminates inauthentic motivation. Individuals fall into bad faith when they deny their freedom by claiming to be determined by external causes—biological drives, social roles, or past experiences. In truth, Sartre argues, even these denials are freely chosen stances. Authentic motivation therefore entails lucidity about one’s freedom and responsibility. As he writes, “man is nothing else but what he makes of himself” (Sartre, 2003, p. 29).
Through Sartre, motivation becomes a moral and existential act. It is the ongoing project of defining oneself through choice. The anguish that accompanies freedom is not pathological but revelatory: it exposes the radical openness of human existence. In Sartre’s existential psychology, motivation is not an effect but the creative activity of consciousness projecting meaning into an absurd world.
Merleau-Ponty and Embodied MotivationMaurice Merleau-Ponty deepened phenomenology by situating motivation in the lived body. In Phenomenology of Perception (1945/2012), he argues that consciousness is incarnate and perception is an active engagement with the world. The body is not an object one has but the manner in which one is in the world. Motivation, therefore, is an embodied orientation—what Merleau-Ponty calls motor intentionality. The body’s gestures, movements, and perceptual patterns express a prereflective motivation toward meaningful action.
Merleau-Ponty distinguishes between causal and motivational explanation: causes operate in physical systems, whereas motivations function in the domain of meaning. A melody, for example, is not caused by its notes but motivated by their sense; similarly, human action is motivated by meanings that solicit the body’s response. This relational understanding dissolves dualisms between mind and body, subject and object. Motivation arises in the interworld where perception and significance intertwine.
From this perspective, motivation is not merely conscious willing but embodied responsiveness. Hunger, desire, curiosity, and creativity are not abstract drives but bodily modes of being-toward-the-world. Merleau-Ponty (2012) writes that the body “is our general medium for having a world” (p. 169). Thus, motivation is always situated within a perceptual and affective field shaped by history, culture, and intersubjectivity.
The phenomenology of embodiment profoundly influenced later psychology, anticipating contemporary research on embodied cognition and affective neuroscience. Gallagher and Zahavi (2013) note that “motivation cannot be detached from the embodied and situated character of consciousness” (p. 128). In this view, existential-phenomenological motivation bridges the physiological and the existential without reducing one to the other.
Existential Psychology: Meaning and ResponsibilityThe philosophical foundations of existential-phenomenological motivation were extended into psychology by Viktor Frankl, Rollo May, and Irvin Yalom. Their shared premise is that human beings are motivated by meaning rather than mere pleasure or power.
- Viktor Frankl and the Will to Meaning
Viktor Frankl’s logotherapy interprets motivation as the will to meaning—the fundamental striving to find significance in life. Against the reductionism of Freud’s pleasure principle and Adler’s power motive, Frankl (1959/2006) posits that “man’s main concern is not to gain pleasure or to avoid pain but rather to see a meaning in his life” (p. 115). This orientation is existential: it acknowledges suffering, death, and guilt as unavoidable dimensions of being, yet insists that meaning can still be discovered.
For Frankl, loss of meaning produces the existential vacuum, a state of inner emptiness manifesting as apathy or nihilism. Logotherapy thus aims to reawaken the individual’s awareness of freedom and responsibility. Motivation is rekindled when a person discerns a purpose that transcends self-interest—love, work, or courage in suffering. Frankl’s emphasis on self-transcendence resonates with Husserlian intentionality and Heideggerian care, situating motivation as a movement beyond the self toward meaning.
- Rollo May and Existential Courage
Rollo May (1958, 1981) integrated existential and phenomenological insights into a psychology of creativity and courage. He argued that motivation arises from the tension between possibility and limitation, a dialectic that defines human existence. Anxiety, far from being purely negative, signals awareness of freedom and potential. Authentic motivation, for May, involves confronting this anxiety courageously—choosing to create meaning despite uncertainty.
May’s emphasis on intentionality and choice parallels Sartre’s notion of project while grounding it in the psychological reality of conflict and emotion. Motivation is not a drive toward equilibrium but a struggle toward authenticity. The individual is motivated by the need to affirm being against nonbeing—to participate actively in the unfolding of existence.
- Irvin Yalom and the Existential Givens
Irvin Yalom (1980) identified four existential “givens” that underlie all motivation: death, freedom, isolation, and meaninglessness. Confronting these givens generates existential anxiety, but it also reveals the potential for authentic living. Motivation, in Yalom’s schema, involves transforming anxiety into engagement—accepting mortality, assuming responsibility, and creating connection and purpose. Existential psychotherapy thus becomes a process of awakening the individual’s inherent capacity for meaning.
Together, these psychologists demonstrate that existential-phenomenological motivation is both philosophical and therapeutic. It restores depth to human psychology by recognizing that every act of striving expresses a fundamental confrontation with existence itself.
Temporality and the Structure of Motivational ExistenceTemporality is central to existential-phenomenological motivation. Heidegger (1962) conceives Dasein as essentially temporal: it projects itself into the future, understands itself through the past, and acts within the present. Motivation is therefore not a static force but a temporal unfolding—the way being realizes itself through time.
Phenomenologically, as Zahavi (2005) explains, consciousness is temporally structured through retention (the just-past), protention (the anticipated), and the living present. Motivation arises within this flow as anticipation of possible fulfillment. To be motivated is to be stretched between what has been and what may come; it is the existential tension that sustains selfhood.
This temporal structure explains the inherent anxiety of motivation. Every projection toward the future is haunted by contingency and death. Yet it is precisely this finitude that gives motivation its urgency and authenticity. As Heidegger shows, “being-toward-death” is not morbid fixation but the recognition that existence is finite and therefore meaningful. Motivation thus expresses our capacity to affirm life in the face of mortality—to make choices whose significance lies in their temporality.
Freedom, Responsibility, and AuthenticityFreedom is the cornerstone of existential-phenomenological motivation. Sartre (2003) asserts that human beings are “condemned to be free”—unable to escape the necessity of choice. This radical freedom entails total responsibility: we are the authors of our motives and our meanings. Motivation, therefore, is not something that happens to us but something we do.
Authentic motivation arises when individuals acknowledge their freedom and act in accordance with self-chosen projects. Inauthentic motivation occurs when one surrenders freedom to external authority or social conformity. Heidegger’s das Man and Sartre’s bad faith both describe this evasion of responsibility.
Authenticity does not imply isolation. Merleau-Ponty (2012) reminds us that motivation is intersubjective: it unfolds within the “intercorporeal” field of relationships. Our motives are shaped by others even as we shape them. Genuine motivation thus involves navigating the ambiguity between autonomy and relationality—affirming one’s freedom while recognizing the shared world of meaning.
The Crisis of Motivation in ModernityModern technological society often obscures existential-phenomenological motivation. As Fromm (1947) and Heidegger (1977) warned, instrumental rationality and consumerism reduce human striving to efficiency and possession. Motivation becomes externalized—measured by productivity, consumption, or status—rather than rooted in authenticity and meaning. The result is alienation and nihilism: a pervasive sense that nothing ultimately matters.
Existential-phenomenological thought offers a corrective by re-grounding motivation in being rather than having. To be motivated authentically is to care about the world and one’s place in it, to engage in projects that disclose meaning. In reclaiming this orientation, the individual resists the dehumanizing tendencies of technological modernity and rediscovers the depth of existence.
Implications for Psychology and Human ScienceContemporary psychology increasingly incorporates existential-phenomenological insights. Self-determination theory, for example, distinguishes autonomous from controlled motivation, echoing the existential difference between authenticity and conformity (Deci & Ryan, 2000). Positive psychology’s focus on meaning and purpose (Baumeister & Vohs, 2002) likewise resonates with Frankl’s logotherapy.
Phenomenological methodologies (Giorgi, 2009) continue to enrich qualitative research by describing the lived structure of motivation without reductionism. Such approaches reveal that human motivation cannot be fully understood apart from consciousness, embodiment, temporality, and freedom. Existential-phenomenological motivation thus bridges philosophy and psychology, providing a comprehensive account of human striving as both descriptive and normative.
ConclusionExistential-phenomenological motivation situates the human drive to act within the ontological structure of existence itself. Rooted in Husserl’s intentionality, Heidegger’s care, Sartre’s freedom, and Merleau-Ponty’s embodiment, it interprets motivation as the unfolding of being-in-the-world rather than a causal mechanism. In psychology, this framework manifests as the will to meaning and the courageous affirmation of freedom and responsibility.
To be motivated, from this perspective, is to project oneself toward possibilities within the horizon of finitude—to seek meaning where none is guaranteed. Motivation becomes a revelation of what it means to exist: the ceaseless movement of consciousness and body toward significance. In an era dominated by instrumental values, existential-phenomenological motivation reminds us that the deepest motive is not to possess or achieve but to be—authentically, responsibly, and meaningfully—in the world." (Source: ChatGPT 2025)
ReferencesBaumeister, R. F., & Vohs, K. D. (2002). The pursuit of meaningfulness in life. Handbook of Positive Psychology, 608–618.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits: Human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11(4), 227–268.
Frankl, V. E. (2006). Man’s search for meaning (I. Lasch, Trans.). Beacon Press. (Original work published 1959)
Fromm, E. (1947). Man for himself: An inquiry into the psychology of ethics. Rinehart.
Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2013). The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science (2nd ed.). Routledge.
Giorgi, A. (2009). The descriptive phenomenological method in psychology: A modified Husserlian approach. Duquesne University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Harper & Row. (Original work published 1927)
Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology and other essays (W. Lovitt, Trans.). Harper & Row.
Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (D. Carr, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.
Husserl, E. (2012). Ideas: General introduction to pure phenomenology (W. R. Boyce Gibson, Trans.). Routledge. (Original work published 1931)
May, R. (1958). Existence: A new dimension in psychiatry and psychology. Basic Books.
May, R. (1981). Freedom and destiny. W. W. Norton.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception (D. A. Landes, Trans.). Routledge. (Original work published 1945)
Moran, D. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. Routledge.
Sartre, J.-P. (2003). Being and nothingness (H. E. Barnes, Trans.). Routledge. (Original work published 1943)